Discourse on the Method


Place on List:

IV. Special Area: Literary Social Criticism

4. Secondary Readings

René Descartes. Discourse on the Method.



Key Terms (tags): certainty, doubt, scepticism, enlightenment, reasoning,



Supporting References:






  1. Cottingham, John. "Cogito ergo sum." The Oxford Companion to Philosophy. : Oxford University Press, 2005. Oxford Reference. 2005. Date Accessed 3 Sep. 2013 .



Perhaps the most celebrated philosophical dictum of all time, Descartes's ‘I am thinking, therefore I exist’ is the starting-point of his system of knowledge. In his Discourse on the Method (1637) Descartes observes that the proposition je pense, donc je suis is ‘so firm and sure that the most extravagant suppositions of the sceptics [are] incapable of shaking it’. The dictum, in its better-known Latin version, also occurs in the Principles of Philosophy (1644). In the Meditations (1641), the canonical phrase does not occur, but Descartes argues instead that ‘I am, I exist is certain as often as it is put forward or conceived in the mind.’ Descartes later observed that the meditator's indubitable awareness of his own existence was ‘recognized as self-evident by a simple intuition of the mind’. There is a partial anticipation of Descartes's Cogito in Augustine, De Civitate Dei, 11. 26.



  1. "Descartes, René." Dictionary of the Social Sciences. Ed. Calhoun, Craig. : Oxford University Press, 2002. Oxford Reference. 2002. Date Accessed 22 Aug. 2013 .



The following focuses on the author and not the text.



“Descartes, René (1596–1650) A French mathematician and philosopher who inaugurated a long tradition of inquiry into mind–body dualism and the conditions of knowledge. Descartes's search for a set of principles that would provide certain knowledge about the world marked him as a rationalist, although not all of his work fit easily into this category. Descartes was born in France but spent much of his career in Holland, where he pursued his interest in mathematics—especially geometry—and where he undertook to develop a unified and rigorous philosophical system. His first major effort in this direction was an elaboration of Copernicus's physics and cosmology, entitled Le Monde. When Descartes learned that Galileo had been condemned by the Inquisition for similar efforts, he suppressed the work and turned to the question of knowledge.



“Much of Descartes's method was based on the apparent certainty and universality of mathematics—a topic he addressed in Discourses on the Method (1637). There he introduced the famous notion of Cogito ergo sum (“I think, therefore I am”), which he asserted was the kernel of certainty that underlay all subsequent claims to knowledge. In response to criticisms of his positions, Descartes undertook a much more thorough elaboration of his method and epistemology in Meditations on First Philosophy (1641). There, he proposed a systematic solution to the problem of uncertainty and offered a response to empiricist claims that knowledge was limited to what was received by the senses. The certainty that one is conscious provides the starting point, he suggested, from which other assertions can be proved. He ran into difficulty, however, in acknowledging that all other knowledge might be illusory. Descartes worked around this problem by developing a notoriously flimsy proof of the existence of God to establish the validity of further knowledge claims, based on God's gift to man of “clear and distinct” concepts, such as mathematics.



“The difficulties raised by Cartesian dualism—the distinction of mind and body (or thought and action)—have been among the main preoccupations of the philosophical tradition and can be said, in many respects, to have inaugurated philosophical modernity. The body was the province of the physical sciences—the study of extension and movement—and Descartes's work gave impetus to that scientific project. The mind, in contrast, belonged to the realm of theology and metaphysics. In later years, Descartes sought to work around some of the difficulties that his ideas had raised, such as the need for some connection between the mind and body (which he thought might reside in the pineal gland). As the leading philosopher of the day, his Meditations (1641) were critically engaged by his contemporaries, including Thomas Hobbes, Pierre Gassendi, and Antoine Arnauld.



“Descartes recapitulated and expanded on his philosophy in The Principles of Philosophy (1644). He also wrote a more eclectic study of psychology, physiology, and morals, entitled Passions of the Soul (1649).”


  1. Birch, Dinah. "Descartes, René." The Oxford Companion to English Literature. : Oxford University Press, 2009. Oxford Reference. 2009. Date Accessed 3 Sep. 2013 .



Descartes, René (1596–1650). French philosopher and mathematician. After a period of travel, in 1629 he decided to devote himself to philosophy and settled in the Netherlands, where he remained until 1649, when he accepted an invitation to visit Sweden, where he died. His main works are: Discours de la méthode (1637: Discourse on the Method), Méditations philosophiques (published in Latin in 1641, in French in 1647: Philosophical Meditations), Principes de la philosophie (published in Latin in 1644, in French in 1647: The Principles of Philosophy), and Les Passions de l'âme (1649: Passions of the Soul). The influence of these on European thought has been considerable. Philosophically his starting point is the problem of certainty posed by *Montaigne's radical scepticism: in other words, the need for a method that establishes reliable propositions. Rejecting the accumulated preconceptions of the past through a process of systematic doubt, he proposes to reconstruct the whole of philosophy on the basis of certain self‐evident truths, including notably the existence of the self in consciousness, the famous ‘cogito ergo sum’ (‘I think, therefore I am’). From this basis he attempts to deduce the existence of God as guarantor of the reliability of the perceptible world, and thus of its susceptibility to scientific analysis. As a mathematician (he made major contributions to algebraic notation and coordinate geometry), he considered mathematical reasoning to be applicable to the whole of science. Although his astronomical theories were demolished by Isaac *Newton, his reduction of matter to the quantifiable has remained fundamental to science. In epistemology and ethics, his rigorous mind–body dualism has similarly been immensely influential. See S. Gaukroger, Descartes (1995).



  1. Buchanan, Ian. "Enlightenment." A Dictionary of Critical Theory. : Oxford University Press, 2010. Oxford Reference. 2010. Date Accessed 3 Sep. 2013 .



Enlightenment (Aufklärung). A broad intellectual movement in Europe characterized by a foregrounding of the power of reason and a setting aside of superstition. There is no consensus as to when exactly the Enlightenment began, but it is not generally thought to have started much before the publication in 1637 of René Descartes's Discours de la méthode pour bien conduire sa raison, et chercher la verité dans les sciences (Discourse on the Method of Rightly Conducting One's Reason and of Seeking Truth in the Sciences), in which the famous slogan celebrating the centrality of reason ‘Je pense, donc je suis’ (I think, therefore I am) appears. Other highpoints include: The Encylopédistes, the group of authors led by Denis Diderot and Jean le Rond d'Alembert who wrote the massive Encyclopédie, ou dictionnaire raisonné des sciences, des arts et des metiers (Encyclopedia, or a systematic dictionary of the sciences, arts, and crafts), between 1751 and 1772, with the express purpose of changing the way people think by foregrounding scientifically acquired knowledge and banishing superstition; the Scottish Enlightenment, contemporaneous with the Encylopédistes, whose leading figures were David Hume, Adam Smith, and Robert Burns ; in the US the group of statesmen who wrote the bill of rights were also considered part of the Enlightenment movement. In critical theory, however, Enlightenment is usually dated by the publication in 1784 of Immanuel *Kant's essay ‘Beantwortung der Frage: Was ist Aufklärung?’ (Answering the Question: What is Enlightenment?), which famously defines Enlightenment as the coming to an end of humanity's period of intellectual immaturity. See also dialectic of enlightenment.



  1. Kirwan, Christopher. "reasoning." The Oxford Companion to Philosophy. : Oxford University Press, 2005. Oxford Reference. 2005. Date Accessed 3 Sep. 2013 .



  1. a
  2. a
  3. a


Comments

Popular Posts